-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 3
/
Copy pathAction Theory Resolving Problems.txt
1041 lines (1031 loc) · 91.8 KB
/
Action Theory Resolving Problems.txt
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
Action Theory Resolving Problems
Open sidebar
Action Theory Resolving Problems
Model: GPT-4
Summarize: mrormanion Theory and the Problem of Action
85
was to guarantee that the behavior issued from that intention and no
other source. The idea was to ensure that no deviant causal chains occur. Mele (1992) correctly objected to this approach, however, on the grounds that people's intentions are not usually that explicitly specified. Instead, itwill be recalled, Mele attempted to explain action as the effects of ongoing intentions. However, he provided no account of causality that incorporates the sustaining and guiding features that such intentions would
require.
Viewed from an information-theoretic perspective, appeals to self-referentiality are attempts to ensure that equivocation does not compro-
mise information flow from intention to execution. Requiring that action
be unequivocal accommodates the spirit of the self-referentiality thesis, as does thinking of action as information flow. By defining action not as the effects of a special type of efficient cause, but as the unequivocal flow of an intention's content from cognitive source to behavioral terminus, wayward causal chain objections can be preempted, In part II, T will flesh out
this idea in more detail, but before doing so, it is important to show how thinking of an action as an uncompromised trajectory from intentional source to behavioral outcome-a flow whose integrity can be determined by calculating the presence of noise and equivocation-can satisfactorily
handle many of the problems on which causal and behaviorist accounts of action have floundered
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
The text discusses a theory concerning the problem of action and how intentions influence behavior. Previously, the dominant approach was to ensure behavior originates from an intention and no other source, thus preventing deviant causal chains. Mele (1992) criticized this view, arguing that people's intentions are usually not so explicitly specified. Instead, he suggested that action should be seen as the effects of ongoing intentions but failed to provide a causality account incorporating these intentions' guiding and sustaining features.
The text then introduces an information-theoretic perspective, where the self-referentiality of intentions is meant to ensure the uncorrupted flow of information from intention to action. Here, action is redefined as the unequivocal flow of an intention's content from the cognitive source to the behavioral terminus, not merely as the effects of a specific efficient cause. This perspective, the author suggests, is capable of preempting objections related to wayward causal chains.
The text indicates that thinking of action as an unbroken trajectory from the intentional source to the behavioral outcome can resolve many of the problems plaguing causal and behaviorist accounts of action. The trajectory's integrity can be determined by calculating the presence of noise and equivocation. The author hints at a more detailed exploration of this idea in the following section.
1 / 1
Chapter 13
Threading an Agent's Control Loop through the
Environment
Recapitulation
In chapters 11 and 12, I postulated that dynamical process es homologous
to those of self-organizing, far-from-equilibrium ablotic and biological
systems are also at work in people and their mental states . In response
to disequilibrium either within an agent 's own cognitive organization or
between the agent 's cognitive state and other internal dynamics (psychological
, emotional, desiderative , motor, and the like), a person 's current
frame of mind can undergo a phase change and recalibrate to rectify the
disequilibrium.62
Formulating a prior intention is just such a catastrophic bifurcation.
Since the neurological system can be conceptualized as a multidimensional
, dynamic landscape , we can think of this process in terms of plate
tectonics and resulting earthquakes . When agents formulate a prior intention
, the establishment of second -order contextual constraints dissipates
the disequilibrium by reorganizing a more complex region of cognitive
and affective space . By imposing new propensities on available pathways,
the dynamics of that newly self-organized semantic space constrain (top-
down) movements within it. Through the assignation of conditional
probabilities, some act-types (some chutes ) are eliminated altogether;
others are made more likely. Then, and as a result of further interaction
among the prior intention, other internal dynamics , and the environment
, one option from those weighted alternatives established by the
new organization becomes a proximate attractor . By entraining motor
dynamics to its own, this pathway directs and constrains action in the
immediate future. And so the person acts .
But not all actions are performed as a result of explicit deliberation. If
in order to choose among the various alternatives available, agents first
needed to implement a decision procedure to determine whether each
option was meaningful , any behavior would be indefinitely delayed . If
agents first had to consider and evaluate every basic act-type A for its
significance , efficiency , parsimony, and other characteristics with respect
to the intended nonbasic behavior A ', they would never act. We saw in
Freeman's (1991a, 1991b) research on odors, Damasio's (1994) hypotheses
about the role of emotions in cognition , and even Hinton 's (1992)
and Elman's (1995) artificial networks , that the context in which stimuli
are experienced or presented plays a primary role in dynamically fixing
their identification . Does something similar happen with intention and the
way it is implemented in behavior ?
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
Chapter 13 discusses how dynamical processes similar to self-organizing systems in abiotic and biological entities are also at work in people and their mental states. It posits that when there's a disequilibrium within an individual's cognitive organization or between their cognitive state and other internal dynamics (psychological, emotional, etc.), the person's frame of mind can undergo a phase change and recalibrate to rectify the disequilibrium.
The formulation of a prior intention is compared to a catastrophic bifurcation within a system. This process can be thought of in terms of plate tectonics causing earthquakes, with the brain as the landscape. When agents formulate a prior intention, it dissipates the disequilibrium by reorganizing a more complex region of cognitive and affective space. This new organization establishes new constraints and propensities, limiting and directing actions.
However, the text acknowledges that not all actions stem from explicit deliberation. If agents needed to implement a decision procedure to evaluate the relevance and efficiency of each action option, any behavior would be indefinitely delayed. The author points to research showing that the context in which stimuli are experienced plays a primary role in dynamically fixing their identification, raising the question if something similar happens with intention and the way it's implemented in behavior.
1 / 1
Intentions "Ain 't Just in the Head" Either
Dynamical systems theory tells us that because they are embedded in history
as well as in a structured environment , people are not independent ,
isolated atoms just plunked into a completely alien environment that
affects them through mechanical forces. As we saw earlier, by means of
second-order context -dependencies established by persistent interaction
with the environment , agents effectively import the environment into
their internal dynamics by recalibrating these to incoming signals. Over
time, that is, both phylo genetic ally and developmentally , people establish
interdependencies between the environment and their internal dynamics
such that the former becomes part of their external structure : their boundary
conditions . Context -sensitive constraints established by positive feedback
weave both the environment and history into the agent's cognitive
and conative states, thereby achieving the embeddedness in space and
time that characterizes those complex systems. The way adaptive systems
function therefore strongly suggests that, as dynamical structures, intentions
"ain' t just in the head" either.
Consider flies. A control loop runs directly from their feet and the surface
on which they are standing to their wings . As a result, the fly does
not need to figure out how to fly ; it needs only to decide what to do
(jump ). Once the fly senses the change in the surface under its feet, the
wings immediately and automatically flap (reported in McClamrock
1995). So only one decision is required : jump now . The external portion
Threading an Agent's Control Loop through the Environment 197
maneuver, we might not even remember whether the traffic light on our
daily commute at the intersection of Elm and Maple was red this morning .
Does that imply that driving was not our action? Of course not .
The picture theory of meaning came under fire as a consequence of
articles by Quine (1953) and Putnam (1975), who revolutionized epis-
temology by arguing that "meanings just ain't in the head" (227). What a
word means is no longer considered just a picture in the head; it is now
thought to be intimately associated with how the word was learned, its
causal history , what it is associated with , and similar factors. Empirical
evidence from other complex adaptive systems, too, attests to the envi-
ronment's role in the way they self-organize . Whether the subject is
motor coordination , olfaction , or auditory perception , importing history
and context into the organism by recalibrating its dynamics is necessary
before those complex skills can develop . Even artificial neural networks
appear to construct semantic, representational spaces when ongoing
feedback embeds them in their environment and their history . Figure 11.1
captured the way the network 's pattern of connection weights reset and
organized to the stimuli on which it was trained.
of the fly 's control loop (what I have called its external structure ) takes
care of the rest.
Homologously , we can suppose that once human agents settle on a
prior intention , the control loop of the intention 's external structure
threads through other attractors and self-organized neurological regions
such as those embodying psychological and emotional properties . The
overall context in which the prior intention is located can therefore be
expected to add its own blases to those of the prior intention . As we saw,
Oamasio (1994) postulates that the cognitive system simplifies its activ-
ities by linking up with the affective system. The entrainment provides
the biasing that imposes additional context -sensitive constraints on the
decision-making and motor systems. As a result, given a particular environment
, some behaviors will automatically be assigned a higher probability
; others will be ruled out. This spares the cognitive , intentional level
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
This section discusses how intentions, like people, are not independent entities. It proposes that intentions, akin to human beings, are embedded in history and structured environments. Over time, both phylogenetically and developmentally, individuals establish interdependencies between the environment and their internal dynamics, making the former part of their external structure, their boundary conditions.
This viewpoint mirrors the dynamical systems theory's perspective, which argues that the external environment and an agent's history are woven into the agent's cognitive and conative states through context-sensitive constraints established by positive feedback. This perspective extends to intentions, which are suggested not to be solely contained "in the head," but are also influenced by external factors.
The text provides the example of flies to illustrate this point. A control loop runs directly from a fly's feet and the surface it's standing on to its wings. This means that the fly only needs to decide to jump; the automatic response of the wings to flap is taken care of by the control loop.
This concept is extended to humans, arguing that once a prior intention is decided, its control loop threads through other attractors and self-organized neurological regions, incorporating psychological and emotional properties. This integrated context biases the prior intention and provides additional context-sensitive constraints on decision-making and motor systems. This process allows the cognitive, intentional level to assign higher probabilities to certain behaviors automatically given a particular environment.
The author also discusses the idea that the meaning of words is not just contained "in the head" but is influenced by how the word was learned, its causal history, and associated factors, providing empirical evidence from complex adaptive systems that import history and context into the organism's dynamics. This argument further supports the concept of intentions being influenced by external factors and not just existing "in the head."
1 / 1
Explaining Self-Organizing Systems through Hermeneutics
Within Stable States
Random fluctuations and perturbations are critical to complex dynamical
systems only at instability thresholds far from equilibrium . During dynamically
stable periods between bifurcation points , even complex systems
follow pathways their attractors carve out. Between phase changes,
therefore, one can forecast that a complex system will select an alternative
from the range described by its attractor 's thickness and shape. Far from
being a substantive prediction , however , this statement amounts to little
more than a tautology . Because complex systems are sensitive to initial
conditions , irregularities and fluctuations in behavior will be so significant
that any specific prediction of the next move will be practically useless.
And the more complex the system, the less the prediction will tell you,
even between phase changes. Since the individual trajectories of systems
can diverge dramatically even while constrained by a strange attractor
(just look again at figure 10.3), explaining why a complex system took
the particular path it did will therefore always require interpretation .
When nonlinear interactions result in interlevel relationships like those
described in previous chapters, the meaning of individual events can be
fully understood only in context : in terms of the higher -level constraints
(the dynamics) that govern them. I propose that explaining complex systems
, including human beings and their actions, must therefore proceed
Narrative Explanation and the Dynamics of Action 223
hermeneutically , not deductively . In textual interpretation "the anticipation
of meaning in which the whole is envisaged becomes explicit understanding
in that the parts, that are determined by the whole , themselves
also determine this whole " (Gadamer 1985, 259). Interpreters must move
back and forth : the whole text guides the understanding of individual
passages ; yet the whole can be understood only by understanding the
individual passages . This interlevel recursiveness, characteristic of hermeneutics
, is thus "a continuous dialectical tacking between the most local of
local detail and the most global of global structure in such a way as to
bring both into view simultaneously " (Geertz 1979, 239). The interlevel
tacking of the hermeneutic "circle" reproduces the self-organization of
complex dynamical process es. By showing the dynamics of complex
adaptive systems, hermeneutical narratives are uniquely suited as the logic
of explanation of these strange-loop phenomena.
The logic of explanation of hermeneutics is therefore appropriate for
explananda whose very nature is a product of that strange circle of whole
and part. In contrast to covering laws and algorithms and deductions
therefrom , that is, interpretation or hermeneutics reproduces the very
logic of nature's open, adaptive dynamics. Like intentional actions, interpretations
are characterized by strange-loop , interlevel relations and are,
in consequence, essentially contextual and historical . Interpretations
therefore explain by showing those nonlinear , interlevel process es at
work . Reversing Kant's epistemological turn, which privileged epistemol-
ogy over ontology , Prigogine 's followers occasionally make the claim
that science operates the way nature does, with parts constituting wholes
that in turn provide the contextual framework for those components . My
explicit claim here is only that human actions and. their explanations do.71
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
This section posits that the behavior of complex dynamical systems, such as human beings and their actions, is best explained through hermeneutics - the interpretation of texts and symbolic expressions. The author proposes that, like complex systems, explanations must proceed hermeneutically rather than deductively.
Random fluctuations and perturbations are crucial to these systems only at instability thresholds far from equilibrium. During stable periods, even complex systems follow pathways carved out by their attractors, but this doesn't allow for substantive prediction due to the systems' sensitivity to initial conditions and the potential for dramatic divergence of individual trajectories within the system.
The author likens the process of interpretation to understanding these systems' trajectories. Interpreters must move back and forth between the whole text and individual passages, a process described as a "continuous dialectical tacking." This same recursive process mirrors the self-organization of complex dynamical systems, suggesting that hermeneutical narratives are well-suited to explain the dynamics of these systems.
The logic of explanation of hermeneutics is seen as appropriate for phenomena whose nature is a product of the circle of whole and part. The interpretative, or hermeneutic, process reproduces the logic of nature's open, adaptive dynamics and helps to illuminate nonlinear, interlevel processes at work. The author also suggests a shift from privileging epistemology over ontology, advocating for a view that parts constitute wholes that in turn provide the contextual framework for those components.
1 / 1
The threat of relativism lurking in the hermeneutic circle has often
encouraged philosophers to reject it . By drawing the explainer and the explanation
into its strange loop , hermeneutics appears to forestall the possibility
of any claim to truth and certainty . If we live in a dynamical universe,
the novelty and creativity such complex systems display do indeed signal
the end of eternal, unchanging , and universal certainty . Unlike modern
science, however , dynamical systems theory provides an understanding of
both the construction and integrity of wholes that does not dissolve their
unity at that level. According to Gadamer (1985), the resolution to the
circularity of hermeneutics is found in Heidegger 's recognition that "the
circle of the whole and the part is not dissolved in perfect understanding
but on the contrary , is most fully realized" (261).
Reconstructing the Origin We make sense of persons and their actions
through just such an interpretive dialectic between wholes and parts.
Consider the hermeneutical flavor that permeates the following approach,
adapted from Rueger and Sharp (1996). From descriptions of the dynamics
of a particular instance of behavior it might be possible to reconstruct
the agent's character or personality and therefore the intention that constrained
the behavior . We can then examine other examples of that per-
son's behavior to see whether the character that these additional examples
suggest corresponds to the personality we inferred earlier. If the test is
positive , we reason ably conclude that the first behavior was "in character."
As a result, we judge it to have been the agent's action and hold him or
her responsible.
From empirically available information of a behavioral output 1(r), and
taking care to note any interference from noise or equivocation , the
explainer attempts to reconstruct 1(5), the cognitive source from which
the behavior issued. The explainer attempts, in other words , to determine
the mental dynamics from which a given instance of behavior flowed
and the particular intentional attractor that constrained it. The purpose of
examining several examples of behavior is to fashion an interpretation
of the unknown dynamics (the intention ) that constrained the particular
behavior in question . The explainer then checks his or her interpretation
of the agent's character by examining whether subsequent behaviors fit
that initial (always tentative ) interpretation .
"How does Rueger and Sharp's procedure differ from any behaviorist 's?"
someone might object . The answer goes as follows : (1) Between phase
changes a complex system's behavior is governed by both the combined
constraints of its own internal dynamics and the initial and ongoing conditions
in which it finds itself . As a result, in contrast to the covering -law
model, the direction of explanatory primacy in interpretation is not the
usual downward , reductive direction (Wimsatt 1976). It moves up and
down levels, from whole to parts, from inside to outside, and vice versa.
This tacking reproduces the interlevel onto logical process es that created
the explanandum. (2) In contrast to behaviorist analyses that attempt to
bypass the subject's actual mental state, moreover , the hermeneut-
explainer tries to reconstruct the particular internal dynamics from which
the actual behavior issued, not bypass those dynamics . (3) Wright (1976)
claimed that only the impact of the mental event must be taken into
account; this impact, however , could not be determined through commonalities
across stimuli -response patterns of behavior over time. Because
complex attractors are often implicated in human actions, differences in
behavior are sometimes more informative than commonalities . Variations
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
This passage addresses potential criticisms of the hermeneutic circle, particularly its alleged tendency to encourage relativism and obstruct objective truth claims. It suggests that, while the dynamical universe's novelty and creativity indeed challenge the concept of unchanging and universal certainty, dynamical systems theory allows for understanding the construction and unity of wholes without undermining their integrity.
The author suggests that we make sense of persons and their actions through an interpretive dialectic between wholes and parts. This process involves interpreting a person's character or personality based on their behavior, and then using additional examples of behavior to confirm or adjust the interpretation. The intention is to uncover the cognitive source or mental dynamics from which a given behavior emerged, and the particular intentional attractor that constrained it.
The author differentiates this approach from behaviorism by pointing out several key differences:
Unlike the downward, reductive direction of explanation in behaviorism, the hermeneutic approach moves up and down levels, from whole to parts, from inside to outside, and vice versa, mirroring the ontological processes that created the explanandum.
While behaviorist analyses often bypass the subject's actual mental state, the hermeneutical approach seeks to reconstruct the particular internal dynamics from which the actual behavior issued.
The author also highlights that it's important to consider the impact of the mental event in the explanation. They note that in human actions, where complex attractors are often involved, variations in behavior can sometimes be more informative than commonalities.
1 / 1
were untrue illusions, poets the "mothers of lies." Philosophers and scientists
thus usurped the bard's divine authority by substituting for the concretely
and messily real the absolutely and abstractly Real . Despite his
respect for the individual and the embodied , even Aristotle gave pride of
place to the eternal and universal. Through philosophical and scientific
reflection, thinkers were expected to dismiss the here and now, discard all
indexical references , and tap into Universal Truth, which exists only in
eternity. Parmenides had won.
In contrast, the logical form of mythic narrative, "In the beginning ... ,"
was both temporal and contextual. Not only did mythic narrative regard
change and place as onto logically real. Myth also recognized the epis-
temological role of such connections : in all stories , time and context are
the crucially necessary cues for decoding the narrative's meaning (Eco
1990). As Proust's descriptions of madeleines and Flaubert 's of dinner
parties also vividly illustrate, stories explain in virtue of their rich
descriptions , which trace the multiple temporal and contextual connections
woven into the very being of a particular event.
Definition, on the other hand, with its eternal unchanging definiens ,
aligned itself with the universal and general , with the eternal and absolutely
true "one," which can only be so in abstraction from the profuse
variation of contingent detail exhibited by the "many." Symbolic logic
and mathematics advanced this trend away from time and context as their
abstract notations put more and more distance between formal systems
and the messy here and now. Newtonian science and covering-law theories
of explanation followed in this tradition. And so for 2,000 years , the
search continued for a perfect, that is, a universal , language (Eco).
But neither the universal nor the abstract explains the particular as such
when that particular is an open, dynamical system far from equilibrium.
Discarding the unique characteristics that time and context impress on
natural phenomena in favor of universal and eternal essences , therefore ,
had an additional consequence : the very contingent details exhibited by
the "many"-those idiosyncratic characteristics and vicissitudes that make
each individual unlike any other-disappeared from ontology and epis-
temology as well. When time and context are banished , in other words,
individuality is banished as well. Despite his claim that individuals are the
only true substance , as we saw, even Aristotle was unable to break entirely
with this approach and carve out a scientific role for the idiosyncracies of
time and place , or for the peculiar -and creative-circularity of selfcause
. Philosophy in general , and action theory in particular, have been
living with the consequences
ever since .
Narrative Explanation and the Dynamics of Action 243
Chapter 14
244
Rehabilitating a narrative logic of explanation as I have attempted in
this chapter will be necessary if we are ever going to pay more than lip
service to the individual . For centuries philosophers have spoken with a
forked tongue : one the one hand they have praised and admired the free,
unique individual ; on the other the universal and repeatable were considered
the only grounds for scientific respectability . Dynamical systems
theory 's value is that it does not zero in solely on the individual at the
expense of the context or larger whole in which the individual is em-
bedded. Nor does it dismiss the individual and unique in favor of the
general and the repeatable. Both are given equal billing . Many implications
follow from this position . The book's last chapter will offer a cursory
survey of some of the social and political consequences that flow from
this theory -constitutive metaphor
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
In this passage, the author argues against the idea of universal, unchanging truths, suggesting that philosophers and scientists historically have substituted the "concretely and messily real" for the "absolutely and abstractly Real." This essentially dismisses the reality of the individual, the here and now, and unique details of time and context.
In contrast, mythic narratives value change, context, and time as ontologically real. They utilize these elements as crucial cues for interpreting meaning. These narratives explain through their rich descriptions which trace temporal and contextual connections.
The author then criticizes the eternal, unchanging essence proposed by definitions, symbolic logic, mathematics, Newtonian science, and covering-law theories of explanation. These entities align with the universal and eternal, abstracting from the unique details that make individuals or events distinct. In doing so, the individuality and idiosyncrasies are effectively banished from ontology and epistemology.
The author advocates for rehabilitating a narrative logic of explanation, which values both the individual and the context in which they exist. This isn't about focusing only on the individual at the expense of the larger whole or dismissing the unique in favor of the general. Both are considered equally important. This perspective carries various implications, and the author proposes to examine some of its social and political consequences in the last chapter of the book.
1 / 1
The book we are discussing is called, dynamics in action by Alicia Juarrero
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
"Dynamics in Action" by Alicia Juarrero is an exploration of how complex systems, such as human action, can be understood through the lens of dynamical systems theory. In this work, Juarrero draws on fields like philosophy, cognitive science, and complexity theory to present a novel understanding of intentional human actions.
In the portions of the book you've shared, Juarrero discusses the interpretive approach of hermeneutics as a way of understanding complex systems, arguing that it mirrors the self-organizing nature of these systems. In particular, she proposes that understanding the actions of individuals and their larger systems should proceed hermeneutically, not deductively. This perspective means that one must consider the contextual, historical, and contingent details that shape actions and behaviors.
Juarrero also contrasts this view with traditional philosophies that privilege universal, eternal truths over the contextual and temporal details that characterize individual actions and experiences. She suggests that this traditional view, which abstracts away the contingent details of individual experiences, fails to capture the complexity and individuality inherent in human action.
In her conclusion, Juarrero advocates for a narrative approach that balances respect for the individual with the context in which they exist, moving away from reductionist perspectives that emphasize either the individual or the collective at the expense of the other. This shift, she suggests, has important implications for social and political thought.
1 / 1
What do you think the difference between hermeneutical and reductive approaches would be?
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
The key difference between hermeneutical and reductive approaches lies in the methodologies used and the scope of understanding they provide, particularly in the context of understanding complex systems.
Hermeneutical Approach:
This method of understanding emphasizes the interpretation of a system's components in relation to their context and the whole system itself. The term 'hermeneutics' originates from biblical and literary studies, where it refers to the interpretation of texts. In the context of understanding complex systems, a hermeneutical approach would involve interpreting the behaviors and interactions of the system's components in light of their broader context and the overall behavior of the system. Hermeneutics thus respects the complexity and context-dependence of system behaviors and is often used in disciplines that deal with complex phenomena, like human actions and societal behaviors. In this approach, the understanding of parts and whole is mutual and recursive, each aspect illuminating the other.
Reductive Approach:
Reductionism is a scientific approach that aims to understand complex systems by breaking them down into their individual components and studying these in isolation. It asserts that the behavior of the whole system can be fully explained by understanding the properties and behaviors of these parts. This method is commonly used in many scientific disciplines, especially in the physical sciences. While the reductive approach has been successful in many domains, it has limitations when applied to highly complex, interdependent systems (such as ecosystems, economies, and human brains), where the interactions among components can give rise to emergent properties that cannot be predicted from the properties of the individual parts alone.
In summary, the main difference between the two approaches is that hermeneutics focuses on interpretation and context, considering the reciprocal influence between parts and the whole, while reductionism focuses on isolating and understanding individual components with the aim of understanding the system as a whole. Both approaches have their strengths and weaknesses, and the choice between them often depends on the nature of the system being studied.
1 / 1
Agency , Freedom , and Individuality
Free Will
It is beyond the scope of this book to examine in detail the implications
with respect to free will suggested by the claim that homologous dynamics
may be at work in all complex dynamical systems , whether autocatalytic
webs, slime molds, or people. However, I wish to note a few salient points.
Despite the numerous attempts to "derive" free will from quantum uncertainty
, the consensus -correct, in my judgment-is that quantum randomness
provides little support for belief in free will; chance is as chancy
a foundation for grounding moral and legal responsibility as is determinism
. We are no more morally responsible for behavior produced by a random
event than for behavior that results from mechanical , forceful causes
operating deterministically . It is just as unwise to attempt to derive free
will from the stochastic nature of some complex adaptive process es. The
macroscopic fluctuation around which a phase change nucleates is as iffy a
basis for imputing agency or moral responsibility as a quantum one.
John Dupre (1993, 216) notes that "[w]hat is problematic about humans
is ... that they are extraordinarily dense concentrations of causal capacity
." In light of this fact, therefore , he proposes that we think of free will
not as the absence of external determining (Newtonian) causes , but as the
human capacity to impose order on a progressively disordered world. The
dynamics of complex dissipative structures support Dupre's proposal. Let
us see why .
Whether a system will reorganize at a new level of complexity or, to
the contrary, will disintegrate , is in principle unpredictable . And if it does
reorganize , the particular form it will take is also in principle unpredictable
. Even if the phase change is fundamentally stochastic , however,
whenever adaptive systems bifurcate, the newly reorganized regime into
which the structure settles (if one is found ) will lower the system 's rate of
internal entropy production even as it increases total entropy production.
So if the system does leap to a more differentiated organization, there will
have been a method to its madness: reorganization always increases complexity
and renews both internal order and overall disorder .
246 Chapter 15
On the view I have been presenting here, imposing order is what all
top-down constraints of dynamical systems do (Pols 1975, 1982). Whether
in autocatalytic cycles or human beings, significance is a result of the
interplay between the system 's own top-down inhibiting constraints and
the alternatives available to its components . In linguistics, constraints sup-
plied by a sentence 's context narrow the potential meaning of individual
words. In genetics , the overall context in which a particular DNA codon
is located affects its phenotypic manifestation . There is no understanding
meaning independently of those interlevel relationships .
Recall the concept of ascendence : Ulanowicz (1997) labeled an organized
entity "ascendent " insofar as it develops as a focus of influence that
grows in cohesion and integrity and thereby withstands the environ-
ment's destabilizing influence . The in-house pruning and streamlining of
autocatalytic webs are carried out in the service of the higher level's focus
of influence . While the system is ascendent , its overarching dynamics
function as its formal cause, constraining the lower levels that make it up.
In that way they ensure the continuity and enhancement of the global
level. In self-organizing, that is, a complex system partly decouples from
the environment, from which it wrests a measure of autonomy. As discussed
in chapters 8 and 9, the difference between the behavior of objects
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
In this section, the author discusses the concept of free will in the context of complex dynamical systems. The text brings up several important points:
Quantum Uncertainty and Free Will: Despite some attempts to connect quantum randomness to free will, the author contends that chance events are not an appropriate basis for grounding moral and legal responsibility. In other words, random behavior at a quantum level doesn't provide us with a satisfying explanation for free will, as it doesn't explain our sense of personal agency and moral responsibility.
Dense Concentrations of Causal Capacity: Humans are viewed as "extraordinarily dense concentrations of causal capacity." This suggests that humans have a unique capacity to cause change and to impose order on the world.
Imposing Order: The author suggests viewing free will not as the absence of external determining causes, but as the human capacity to impose order on an increasingly disordered world. This perspective is supported by the dynamics of complex dissipative structures, systems that maintain and organize themselves by exchanging energy and matter with their environments.
Significance and Context: The significance of a part of a complex system, whether it's a word in a sentence or a DNA codon in an organism, is determined by its context and the overarching system it's a part of. The overall system exerts a top-down constraint that shapes the behavior and meaning of its components.
Ascendence: The author discusses the concept of "ascendence" in complex systems, a term used by Ulanowicz to describe a system's ability to resist environmental instability and develop a focus of influence. In essence, as a system self-organizes, it partially decouples from its environment and gains a degree of autonomy.
The text suggests that free will might be better understood not as a state of being unaffected by determinism or randomness, but as an ability to generate order and influence as part of a self-organizing, complex system. This perspective sees free will as emerging from the complex interplay between a system's components and the system as a whole. It hints at a view of free will that is not entirely deterministic or completely random but is a product of the complex dynamics of human behavior and cognition.
1 / 1
self .
But in a world with room for unique individuals and the creativity and
novelty they promote, precise prediction is impossible -thankfully. And
this is the point the unhappy jurors must not forget. Too often we long
for Newton's simple, clockwork universe , whose unambiguous , tidy formulas
can resolve once and for all our uncertainty. The answer to the
question , "When will the eclipse occur ?" can be determined with astounding
precision : "At 3: 45 P .M . on December 11, 4022." We yearn for a
metaphysics and an epistemology that will provide similar certitude when
answering the question , "Was it first- or second -degree murder, or manslaughter
?" For centuries , the theories of philosophers and scientists
encouraged such yearnings . They are blameless , however (by reason of
ignorance !), for not having understood that such a wish can be granted
only to closed, linear systems, that is, to a determinist universe of cookie-
cutter automata: " answered prayers," indeed.
In a complex world of astronomical dimensionality, the amount of variation
even within regularities is astounding. There may be ethical problems
involved in cloning, but producing identical copies is not one of
them. Not even monozygotic twins are identical , either in appearance or
behavior. It would be a much impoverished world it they were. However,
Chapter 15
260
living in a universe so richly creative as to have produced complex societies
and unique individuals comes at a price. The very dynamics that
allowed us to evolve the capacity to wink , and even to deliberate about
whether we should wink , also prevent us from establishing with absolute
certainty whether someone's past behavior was a wink or a blink , or from
definitively predicting whether he or she will wink in the next few
minutes.
We are enmeshed in a fabric of time and space, which we unravel at
our peril . In part, we are the product of a complex dance between our
innate endowments and an already structured physical and social environment
. We are never passive in this entire process, however . Even the
environment in which we are situated is itself, in part, the downstream
consequence of our own upstream doings, both phylo genetic ally and
onto genetic ally . As such both culturally and individually , we bear a measure
of responsibility for that environment . Once we are mature and
aware, we can self-consciously select the stimuli to which we will respond
and that will affect what and who we are in the future . At that point we
are as responsible for who we will become as is the environment . And
once again, this is true for each of us both as members of a community
and as individuals .
Complex dynamical systems suggest, in other words , that although
there is an onto logical difference between a wink and a blink , and my
vote as a juror will be based on my judgment as to which it was, it may
be impossible to tell definitively and once and for all which was which .
But the alternative is not total ignorance and impotence . We have the
ability both to impart through example and to acquire as an exercise in
personal responsibility the sensitivity to contextual nuances (spatial, historical
, and cultural ) in others and in ourselves that will enable us to better
understand the dynamics and behavior of both . With that ability comes
the obligation to nurture the practical wisdom with which we can make
reasoned, reflective judgments about ourselves and the messy, complex
world in which we live -and to act from that wisdom .
With any luck, we might be more often right than wrong .
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
In this section, Alicia Juarrero discusses the implications of individuality, novelty, and unpredictability in the context of complex dynamical systems. Key points include:
Unpredictability and Individuality: Juarrero suggests that the existence of unique individuals and the novelty they bring makes precise prediction impossible, which she argues is a positive aspect. The uniqueness and variability that come with individuality defy the ability to make exact predictions about human behavior and action, unlike predictable physical phenomena like solar eclipses.
Desire for Certainty: Juarrero critiques our longing for certainty and precision akin to the predictability of Newton's clockwork universe. This wish for certainty can only be granted in a deterministic world, devoid of complex individuality and creativity, a world that Juarrero suggests would be very impoverished.
Complexity and Variation: Juarrero highlights the vast complexity and variability of the world, even within seemingly identical entities such as monozygotic twins.
Time, Space, and Responsibility: We are part of a complex interplay between our innate endowments and the physical and social environment. However, we're not passive participants, we are in part, responsible for our environment and have the capacity to choose the stimuli to which we respond.
Practical Wisdom: Given the complexity of human behavior and our world, it's important to develop sensitivity to contextual nuances and practical wisdom. We are obligated to nurture this wisdom, and to use it in making reasoned, reflective judgments about ourselves and our complex world.
Right more often than Wrong: Finally, Juarrero ends with a hopeful note, suggesting that while absolute certainty might be impossible, with practical wisdom and understanding of the complex dynamics of human behavior, we can hope to be right more often than wrong in our judgments and actions.
1 / 1
Index 283
of a system, 109- 110
ignorance acting in (Aristotle ), 16, 57
independence
divergence of dynamical systems from,
137- 140
individuals and individuation, 8, 44 , 104 ,
219- 222, 243, 259- 260
information
auditory , 148
in autocatalytic and self-organizing
process es , 126
as cause, 94- 97
in communications channel , 8- 9, 88- 90
context-free constraints to encode , 136
created by enabling constraints , 143
entropy as missing , 77
generated by intention, 92- 94
generation of, 190
historical, 8
in phase changes , 235
received (I(r)), 79
at source (1(5)), 78- 79
informational closure , 126
information flow
for behavior to qualify as action, 86
in information theory , 5, 78
from intention to behavior, 82- 86
noise and equivocation in, 79- 81
output and source in trajectory of, 96- 97
relationship between outcome and source ,
81
time stretch es in , 93
information theory
applied to action, 92
constraints in , 133
decision process es in , 77
introduction to , 78- 79
meaningful information, 98
noise and equivocation in, 77, 79- 82
integration
relation to stability , III
of a system , 110- 111
See also coordination of a system 's
components
intentions
act-tokens (basic and non-basic ) generated
by, 29- 30, 32- 34, 92- 94
behaviorist reduction of , 51- 52
in causal theories of action , 34- 35 , 42
contextual constraints in , 7- 8, 186- 188
intentions-in -action (Searle ), 34
robustness of , 250
of individual, 245- 249
of self- organized systems, 249
Furley, Do , 18 , 20
Gadamer, H . G ., 218, 219, 223 , 234, 236,
237
Galileo, 45 , 104
Gardner, Daniel, 171 , 172
Garfinkel, Alan, 39 , 146 , 181
Gatlin, Lila, 6 , 133- 135 , 137 , 143
Geertz, C ., 223
Georgopoulos, A ., 17 I
Gillett, G ., 252
Ginet, C ., 27 , 35 , 200
Godfrey-Smith, P ., 68
Goldman, Alvin, 29- 35 , 205
Goodwin, Brian, 147
Grobstein, C ., I I I , 124
Gruengard, 0., 53- 54 , 182- 184 , 226
Hacker, A ., 1, 237
Haken, H ., 20 , 144
Harman, G ., 84
Harre, R ., 252
Hausheer, R ., 258
Hayies, N . K ., 239
Heck hausen, H ., 34
Heidegger, J. H ., 223
He ' ll, J., 24 , 27
Hempel, C ., 50 , 218, 219
hierarchies
con text -dependent/ contex t- sensi t ive
constraints create, 140
hierarchical systems, 113
structural and control, 114
in a system, 122- 123
Hinton, G ., 164 , 166 , 167 , 172 , 188 , 196 ,
207
history
absent from classical thermodynamics,
104- 105
embeddedness of complex systems in , 219,
221 ,250- 255
in nonequilibrium thermodynamics, 142
role in modern science and philosophy, 219
Hofstadter, D ., 129
holism, 130
Holling, E ., 111
Hume, David, 48- 49 , 56- 59 , 66 , 107
identity
of self- organizing process es , 123- 125
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
The text you provided seems to be an index or table of contents for a book. It's a list of topics covered in the book, along with the pages on which they can be found. The topics range from concepts in information theory, action theory, philosophy, and complex systems to references to various thinkers, including philosophers like David Hume, Gadamer, Heidegger, and scientists like Galileo.
Specific concepts listed include:
"Information": Discussions around information seem to be significant, with different aspects like auditory information, information theory, information flow, and information as a cause being referenced on various pages.
"Individuals and Individuation": The topic of individuality appears to be discussed extensively throughout the book, with references to pages discussing the concept and implications of individuality and individuation.
"Intentions": The book seems to delve into the concept of intentions in great detail, exploring intentions in various contexts such as causal theories of action and behaviorist reduction of intentions.
"Complex systems": The book appears to discuss complex systems at length, touching on their behavior, self-organization, and the role of history and embeddedness in such systems.
References to specific scholars or thinkers, including "Hume, David", "Gadamer, H. G.", "Heidegger, J. H.", and "Galileo", indicating that their thoughts or ideas are discussed or referenced in the book.
Please provide more context or a specific question if you need further information.
1 / 1
It's from the same book.
Explaining Self-Organizing Systems through Hermeneutics
Within Stable States
Random fluctuations and perturbations are critical to complex dynamical
systems only at instability thresholds far from equilibrium . During dynamically
stable periods between bifurcation points , even complex systems
follow pathways their attractors carve out. Between phase changes,
therefore, one can forecast that a complex system will select an alternative
from the range described by its attractor 's thickness and shape. Far from
being a substantive prediction , however , this statement amounts to little
more than a tautology . Because complex systems are sensitive to initial
conditions , irregularities and fluctuations in behavior will be so significant
that any specific prediction of the next move will be practically useless.
And the more complex the system, the less the prediction will tell you,
even between phase changes. Since the individual trajectories of systems
can diverge dramatically even while constrained by a strange attractor
(just look again at figure 10.3), explaining why a complex system took
the particular path it did will therefore always require interpretation .
When nonlinear interactions result in interlevel relationships like those
described in previous chapters, the meaning of individual events can be
fully understood only in context : in terms of the higher -level constraints
(the dynamics) that govern them. I propose that explaining complex systems
, including human beings and their actions, must therefore proceed
Narrative Explanation and the Dynamics of Action 223
hermeneutically , not deductively . In textual interpretation "the anticipation
of meaning in which the whole is envisaged becomes explicit understanding
in that the parts, that are determined by the whole , themselves
also determine this whole " (Gadamer 1985, 259). Interpreters must move
back and forth : the whole text guides the understanding of individual
passages ; yet the whole can be understood only by understanding the
individual passages . This interlevel recursiveness, characteristic of hermeneutics
, is thus "a continuous dialectical tacking between the most local of
local detail and the most global of global structure in such a way as to
bring both into view simultaneously " (Geertz 1979, 239). The interlevel
tacking of the hermeneutic "circle" reproduces the self-organization of
complex dynamical process es. By showing the dynamics of complex
adaptive systems, hermeneutical narratives are uniquely suited as the logic
of explanation of these strange-loop phenomena.
The logic of explanation of hermeneutics is therefore appropriate for
explananda whose very nature is a product of that strange circle of whole
and part. In contrast to covering laws and algorithms and deductions
therefrom , that is, interpretation or hermeneutics reproduces the very
logic of nature's open, adaptive dynamics. Like intentional actions, interpretations
are characterized by strange-loop , interlevel relations and are,
in consequence, essentially contextual and historical . Interpretations
therefore explain by showing those nonlinear , interlevel process es at
work . Reversing Kant's epistemological turn, which privileged epistemol-
ogy over ontology , Prigogine 's followers occasionally make the claim
that science operates the way nature does, with parts constituting wholes
that in turn provide the contextual framework for those components . My
explicit claim here is only that human actions and. their explanations do.71
The threat of relativism lurking in the hermeneutic circle has often
encouraged philosophers to reject it . By drawing the explainer and the explanation
into its strange loop , hermeneutics appears to forestall the possibility
of any claim to truth and certainty . If we live in a dynamical universe,
the novelty and creativity such complex systems display do indeed signal
the end of eternal, unchanging , and universal certainty.
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
This passage is discussing how to explain self-organizing systems, using the approach of hermeneutics, which is a method of interpretation often applied in the humanities, particularly in the interpretation of texts. The author extends its use to understand complex dynamical systems.
In a nutshell, the text argues that complex systems, including human actions, can only be understood hermeneutically, not deductively. This means understanding the system is a process of back-and-forth interpretation between the parts and the whole.
Key points include:
Complex Systems and Sensitivity to Initial Conditions
: The author notes that because complex systems are sensitive to initial conditions, any specific prediction of their behavior will be practically useless due to irregularities and fluctuations.
Hermeneutics and Interpretation
: The author suggests using hermeneutics to understand complex systems. Hermeneutics involves the understanding of a whole by interpreting its parts and understanding the parts in the context of the whole. In this context, it means interpreting the behavior of complex systems by understanding the individual events within the system in relation to the overall dynamics of the system.
Hermeneutics and Nonlinear Interactions
: The author suggests that when nonlinear interactions lead to relationships between different levels of a system, the meaning of individual events can only be fully understood in context: i.e., in terms of the higher-level constraints that govern them.
Dialectical Tacking
: The author introduces the concept of "dialectical tacking," which involves a continuous shifting between the local details and the global structure of the system to bring both into simultaneous view. This concept reflects the self-organization of complex dynamical processes.
Role of Hermeneutics
: The author argues that hermeneutical narratives, which show the dynamics of complex adaptive systems, are uniquely suited to explain these systems.
Reversal of Kant's Epistemological Turn
: The author notes a reversal of Kant's epistemological turn, which prioritized epistemology over ontology, suggesting instead that the behavior of complex systems justifies a focus on ontology, the study of existence and reality.
Relativism and Hermeneutics
: The author addresses the criticism that hermeneutics, by involving the explainer in its interpretive loop, can lead to relativism, where truth and certainty are dismissed. However, the author argues that in a complex, dynamic universe, novelty and creativity are more important than absolute certainty.
1 / 1
It is important , nevertheless, to emphasize that interpretation can discover
only whether a particular instance of behavior was "in character."
That sometimes-perhaps often-it is possible to judge someone's
behavior accurately as being "in character," however , should not lull us
into believing that we have achieved certainty in judging a particular
instance of behavior . That is, when we are dealing with complex adaptive
systems, surprises are unavoidable . Because of their sensitivity to initial
conditions -due, in turn, to their contextual and temporal embeddedness
-complex adaptive systems are characterized by unusual twists and
novel turns. We saw the havoc that equivocation and noise can wreak in
interrupting and compromising an intended trajectory . l (r) can semantically
satisfy 1(5) without being identical to Is(r). And yet circumstantial
evidence often misleads us into supposing that it is. Since we will never
be able to specify any dynamical system's initial conditions to the requisite
(infinite ) degree, a fortiori we will never be able to capture all the
details and circumstances of anyone's life and background . Given this limitation
, we must always keep in mind that reconstructing specific instances
of behavior will always be, at best, an interpretation and not a deduction
-a much more fallible type of explanation than we had previously hoped
was available. Interpretations of human action are always tentative
(Metzger 1995).
Absolute certainty about either what the agent just did, or what he or
she will do-specifically -a year from now, is therefore impossible . As
the title of Prigogine 's latest book (1996) announces, the dynamics of
complex systems signal the end of certainty . The exact trajectory of any
stochastic entity captured by a complex attractor , even between phase
changes, is impossible either to predict or retrodict precisely, even in
principle . It cannot be predicted with exactitude in part because of the
multiple realizability that self-organized systems support and the mischief
that initial conditions wreak, but also because open dynamical systems'
control loop runs partly through the environment , as we saw in the last
chapter. The dramatic fluctuations in behavior that strange attractors
allow make any hope of predicting a dynamical system's specific future
trajectory a futile wish . Knowing someone is ambitious will not tell you
what specific path his or her behavior will take.
Since it is equally impossible to retrodict with absolute precision, what
would a hermeneutic explanation of chapter 5's maverick psychotherapist
Narrative Explanation and the Dynamics of Action 225
look like? Explaining the therapist's behavior as an act-token will require
doing what I did when I presented the proposed counterexample : it will
be necessary to identify and describe the many details and connections
that illustrate how the unusual behavior flowed from and was constrained
by the psychiatrist 's intuition that the moment represented a unique
intersection of events and circumstances. The psychiatrist must describe in
rich and vivid detail her interpretation of the patient 's situation at that
moment , how it had reached that crisis, the history of the relations
between therapist and patient , the unique events that precipitated the
crisis, and so forth . Providing a robust and detailed historical narrative of
all the background and context surrounding the unique moment can suggest
the mental dynamics from which the psychotherapist 's unorthodox
behavior flowed . Describing such concrete details of the entire historical ,
contextually grounded situation allows the explainer to situate the unorthodox
intervention in context (both internal and external) such that the
behavior reveals itself as an act-token, that is, as behavior constrained by
meaning and purpose.
Hermeneutical explanations must begin, that is, by describing the mental
dynamics from which the action flowed into behavior . Recall the earlier
discussion on contrastive stress: "It is the presence or absence of an
alternative in the contrast set taken into account by the agent that draws
the line between his unintentional actions and his non-actions" (Dascal
and Gruengard 1981, 110). This claim has the following implications for
the way actions must be explained : a correct explanation of why X Aed
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
The passage continues the discussion about interpreting complex adaptive systems, focusing now on human behavior. It emphasizes that our understanding of an individual's actions is always interpretation rather than absolute certainty. Here are some of the main points:
Behavior "In Character" and Uncertainty
: The text underlines that the interpretation of behavior can only ascertain if an action was "in character" for the individual in question. However, due to the inherent complexity and sensitivity to initial conditions of human behavior, there can be unexpected outcomes. Interpretation can often lead to misunderstandings, as one might wrongly assume that the observed action represents the usual behavior pattern of the individual.
Limitations and Fallibility of Interpretation
: The author states that since it is impossible to fully understand an individual's initial conditions (i.e., the circumstances and influences that shaped them), our interpretations are, at best, estimates. This is why the author states that interpretations are a "more fallible type of explanation."
End of Certainty
: The author refers to the work of Prigogine, who posited that complex systems mark the end of certainty. Exact predictions or retractions of the behavior of such systems are impossible due to factors such as the influence of initial conditions, the multiplicity of possible outcomes, and the interaction with the environment.
Hermeneutic Explanation of Behavior
: The author proposes using a hermeneutic approach to explain complex behaviors, detailing how to apply it using the example of a maverick psychotherapist. This involves describing the historical and contextual details that influenced the individual's actions and decisions, thereby offering an interpretation of the mental dynamics behind the behavior.
Contrastive Stress and Mental Dynamics
: The author highlights the importance of understanding the presence or absence of alternatives considered by the individual. This helps differentiate between unintentional actions and non-actions, providing further insight into the individual's behavior.
Overall, the passage continues to stress that while hermeneutic explanations provide useful insights into understanding complex behaviors, they should not be misconstrued as providing absolute certainty. The inherent complexity and sensitivity to initial conditions of complex systems (including human behavior) mean that unpredictability and surprises are inevitable.
1 / 1
the system, the more explanatory work the dynamics do; the more
complex the system, the more the initial conditions do. Between phase
changes, on the other hand, it is first necessary to reconstruct the process
that drove the system far from equilibrium . Did the agent's own internal
dynamics drive him or her to a threshold point ? Or was it more a case of
external perturbations driving (the agent's) weak internal dynamics to an
instability ?
There is no one-to-one relationship between the dynamics in place
before the phase change and those that appear after. The direction that a
stochastic dynamical system's bifurcation will take cannot in principle be
predicted even by ideal, omniscient observers. The precise path that the
phase change takes-the addict's sudden resolve to "go clean" rather
than, say, go on methadone-can be explained only after the fact. Such
explanation must take the form of a genealogical narrative that reconstructs
the bifurcation by painstakingly describing (1) the interlevel and
contextual interactions that took the system far from equilibrium in the
first place, (2) the particular fluctuation or perturbation that drove it over
the edge, and (3) the specific pathway that the bifurcation took (as
opposed to other possible alternatives ).
Narrative Explanation and the Dynamics of Action 233
Because storytelling, narrative, and drama can reproduce the creative ,
temporal process of nature in a way that the deductive-nomological
model cannot, Gadamer (1985, 420) states that "the primacy of hearing
is the basis of the hermeneutical phenomenon ." When we listen to a
melody, the notes we hear derive their aesthetic quality from their relationship
to and dependence on the earlier notes. Similarly, a counselor 's
appearance will be meaningful to the addict only in a particular historical
context. Stories retell these temporal, concrete , and particular interactions
in a way that deductive-nomological explanations do not.
In the transformation across stable states , serendipitous events carry
the explanatory load. In contrast to covering-law accounts , hermeneutic
explanations of phase change transformations must therefore make note
of and emphasize the particular case 's concrete and temporal details even
more than when they explain behavior issuing from established dynamics .
The narrative or dramatic reconstruction of those transformations must
describe the role random, unique events and co incidences play. Recovering
addicts often explain their turnaround by pointing to such events:
"I had hit bottom and the counselor just happened by at the right
moment." As historians and novelists have long known, those singular-
ities are often responsible for the turning points in people 's lives. They
serve as the chance fluctuations that can take a system already far from
equilibrium over the edge and cause it to disintegrate. They can also be
the focus around which the new system will nucleate, if it reorganizes at
all . Singularities are thus crucial to the phase changes of historical pro-
cesses constrained by positive feedback and context-dependence . Across
phases , that is, unique events playa pivotal role, thereby complicating the
explainer 's task even more. In short, to explain not only the everyday
genesis of prior intentions but also dramatic personal transformations , it is
often necessary to provide a retrospective and interpretive narrative that
makes ample references to the particular physical, cultural, social , and personal
circumstances that took the individual far from equilibrium. Special
attention must then be given to the unique and chance events that precipitated
the change . Why did the alcoholic quit just now? Any explanation
must identify and interpret these dramatic turning points. "His
daughter , whom he adores , ran into him, dead drunk, at a bar. She had
never seen him like that before and he was devastated."
Genealogical narratives reconstruct the leap that the e .rplal/a I1dum
undergoes at a bifurcation point. If I am correct and forming a prior intention
is just such a phase change , a historical interpretation recounting
both the background conditions and dynamics that led to disequilibrium,
as well as the singular circumstances that precipitated a particular course
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
The passage continues to explore the complexities of interpreting complex adaptive systems like human behavior. It discusses the intricate relationships between dynamics and initial conditions, the unpredictability of phase changes, and the important role of storytelling in understanding these processes. Here are the key points:
Dynamics and Initial Conditions
: The text highlights that the more complex the system, the more the initial conditions contribute to the behavior, whereas in simpler systems, dynamics play a more significant role. The text suggests that it's necessary to understand the process that drove the system away from equilibrium before predicting the behavior between phase changes.
Unpredictability of Phase Changes
: The author notes that there isn't a one-to-one relationship between the dynamics before a phase change and those that appear after. The direction a stochastic dynamical system will take during a bifurcation (or phase change) cannot be predicted, even by an omniscient observer. This can only be explained retrospectively.
Narrative Explanation
: The passage emphasizes the importance of narrative in explaining these complex processes. Hermeneutic explanations, according to the author, should include genealogical narratives that describe the interactions, fluctuations, and specific pathways that led to the phase change.
The Role of Serendipitous Events
: The text discusses the significant role that random, unique events and coincidences play in transformations between stable states. For example, a recovering addict may attribute their turnaround to a serendipitous event. The author asserts that these unique events are critical to phase changes in historical processes.
Retrospective and Interpretive Narrative
: The author argues that to understand not only the everyday formation of intentions but also significant personal transformations, we must provide a narrative that references the specific circumstances that took the individual away from equilibrium. Special attention must be given to unique and chance events that precipitated change.
Genealogical Narratives
: The author suggests that genealogical narratives can help understand the leap that an entity undergoes at a bifurcation point. This would require an interpretation that recounts the background conditions and dynamics that led to disequilibrium, as well as the unique circumstances that precipitated a particular course.
In summary, the passage highlights the complexities of understanding human behavior and the crucial role of narrative, unique events, and context in interpreting these complex processes.
1 / 1
Tiesman, and Charles Bovary drive Nora, Hedda, and Emma to the edge.
David Lewis's Logic of Explanation
Hermeneutic interpretation , within a narrative framework , thus comes
closest to the logic of explanation advocated by David Lewis (1973a).
Twenty -five years or so ago, Lewis argued that causes should be analyzed
in terms of counterfactuals : if x had not occurred, y would not have.
Despite the potential objection , "What underwrites the counterfactual
itself if not causality?" thinking of y in terms of its dependence on x can be
helpful , as we saw with the concepts of equivocation and noise, incapturing
the way meaning flows from intention into action. Remark ably, however
, neither Lewis's ideas on cause nor Wesley Salmon's (1977) claim
that a cause is whatever transmits a mark has found its way into mainstream
philosophy 's literature on action .
The Explainer
In the nineteenth century , hermeneutics attempted to emulate the method
of the natural sciences of the period , "the conquest of mythos by logos"
(Gadamer 1985, 242). As was true of the natural sciences and philosophy
of the time, experimenters and thinkers claimed to be able to detach
themselves from the object of experimentation or analysis. In Schleier-
macher's words , the goal of textual interpretation was "to understand a
writer better than he understood himself " (quoted in Gadamer, 160), a
result purportedly achievable through the application of a "canon of
grammatical and psychological rules of interpretation " (163). Hence the
desire to formulate accurate methodological principles that, when applied
to the obscure object, would render it transparent . Correct hermeneutical
interpretation , in other words , would approach the deductive -nomological
limit .
Complete understanding would be achieved by effectively detaching
the interpreter from the object, text, or behavior under scrutiny . Hence
the claim of nineteenth -century hermeneutics to objective knowledge :
interpreters do not interpret ; like a clear mirror they simply reflect what is
all there, always and objectively , in the text . Nineteenth -century hermeneutics
thus shared with Newtonian science and modern philosophy the
goal of achieving objective , certain, universal knowledge by escaping the
constraints of time and other "anthropological considerations ." As unwit-
Chapter 14
236
If causes are conceptualized in terms of counterfactuals-if x hadn 't
been , y would not have , determining that y depended on , x, which in turn
depended on lV, and so forth -an explanation will explain by retracing
the phenomenon's entire historical trajectory. Providing a genealogical or
historical narrative tracks all those dependencies . But if the dependencies
are due , not to external forces impacting on objects , but to those contextual
constraints that weave the phenomena and process es together into
systematic wholes and then take those very wholes far from equilibrium
and over the edge into a new regime , tracing that genealogy will not
proceed in a simple straight line . A full -bodied historical and interpretive
explanation will require a concrete and detailed narrative that describes
all of those interrelationships. A complete and correct explanation must
reconstruct the entire historical and contextual bramble bush , which it will
do by taking full advantage of the polysemy of narrative or reenactment
to describe the many temporal and spatial interconnections involved.
When it comes to explaining the details of the paths we take , uncharacteristic
behavior , or especially those dramatic turning points in our
lives , Proust and Ibsen will therefore always trump Hume and Hempel
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
This part of the text continues the discussion about how complex systems, such as human behavior, are interpreted and explained, arguing that the explanation needs to take into account the historical, contextual, and singular elements of the system in question. Here are the main points discussed:
David Lewis's Logic of Explanation
: The author discusses David Lewis's perspective that causes should be thought of in terms of counterfactuals - the idea that if one thing hadn't happened, another thing wouldn't have happened. This approach can be beneficial in understanding how meaning flows from intention to action. However, these ideas have not found their way into mainstream philosophical literature on action.
Hermeneutic Interpretation
: The author then delves into the history of hermeneutics, noting its attempts to mirror the method of the natural sciences of the nineteenth century, striving to achieve objective knowledge. However, this approach also tried to detach the interpreter from the object, text, or behavior being analyzed, aiming for a clear reflection of the object itself rather than an interpretation.
The Explainer
: The author critiques this approach, arguing that it oversimplifies the process of interpretation. In reality, understanding complex systems requires reconstructing the entire historical and contextual 'bramble bush' - all the interrelationships and dependencies that contribute to the system's behavior.
Historical Narrative and Context
: If the dependencies are due to contextual constraints and not just to external forces, the process of tracing the system's genealogy becomes more complicated. A complete explanation requires a detailed narrative that encompasses all these elements, providing a full-bodied historical and interpretive account of the system.
The Primacy of Narrative
: Finally, the author posits that when it comes to explaining intricate behaviors or significant turning points in our lives, the narrative method will always trump a more deductive approach. The author suggests that the depth and richness of narrative or dramatic reenactment is more capable of capturing the complex interrelationships involved in human behavior. This position values the insights of artists like Proust and Ibsen over philosophers like Hume and Hempel.
In sum, the text advocates for an approach to explanation that involves a detailed narrative encompassing all the historical, contextual, and singular elements of the system in question, suggesting that this is the most effective way to understand complex systems such as human behavior.
1 / 1
A list of all of the topics we have discussed
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
Here's a summary of the main topics we've discussed based on your series of text excerpts:
Complex Systems and Phase Changes
: We've discussed the idea of complex systems and how their behavior can change dramatically at certain 'threshold points' or phase changes. These phase changes may be driven by either internal dynamics or external perturbations, and the role of these drivers can vary depending on the complexity of the system.
Stochastic Dynamical Systems and Bifurcation
: The specific direction that a stochastic dynamical system's bifurcation (splitting or branching) will take cannot be predicted, even by an ideal observer. This unpredictability introduces a significant element of complexity into the behavior of these systems.
Narrative Explanation and Hermeneutics
: We've examined the importance of narrative explanation and the hermeneutic method of interpretation in understanding complex systems. These techniques emphasize the importance of historical context, singular events, and temporal details in interpreting system behavior.
Counterfactuals and Dependency
: We've discussed David Lewis's idea that causality should be considered in terms of counterfactuals, and how this idea can help to understand dependencies within complex systems.
Genealogical Narratives
: We've delved into the role of genealogical narratives in reconstructing the history of a system's behavior, particularly at points of phase change or bifurcation. These narratives can help to illuminate the complex interplay of factors that drive system behavior.
Role of the Interpreter
: We've talked about the role of the interpreter in understanding complex systems, contrasting the detached perspective of traditional natural science and 19th-century hermeneutics with the more engaged and contextual approach advocated in the text.
Contextual Constraints and Historical Trajectory
: The explanation of a phenomenon involves tracing its historical trajectory and understanding the interrelationships and dependencies formed by contextual constraints.
The Primacy of Narrative
: The author stresses the importance of narrative methods in understanding complex behaviors and major life changes, suggesting that the depth and nuance of narrative or reenactment can capture the complex interconnections involved in human behavior. This highlights the value of literary and dramatic insights over traditional philosophical perspectives.
This is an overarching summary of the topics discussed. Each of these topics are interconnected, illustrating the complexities and intricacies involved in understanding and explaining complex systems, particularly as they pertain to human behavior and historical process.
1 / 1
The author recently wrote a book called Context changes everything
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
As an AI developed by OpenAI, I have knowledge only up until September 2021 and I don't have the ability to search the internet in real-time, so I don't have information about any book titled "Context Changes Everything" written after that time.
However, given our discussion and the excerpts from the text you've shared, it's reasonable to infer that such a book by this author might explore themes like the following:
The Impact of Context
: The book could delve into how different elements of context (e.g., historical, social, cultural) can drastically alter the interpretation and understanding of events or actions.
Interpretation and Understanding
: Drawing from hermeneutic tradition, the book may explore how interpretations of actions, behaviors, or events can shift based on the context in which they occur. It might argue that gaining a full understanding of any event or action requires considering it in its full context.
Complex Systems and Context
: The author could expand on how context influences the behavior of complex systems. This could include discussions of phase changes, bifurcation, and the role of external perturbations.
Narrative Explanation
: The book might further explore the idea of using narratives to explain events or behaviors, emphasizing the importance of temporal and spatial details, and singular events in these narratives.
Context and Change
: The author could discuss how changes in context can lead to dramatic changes in system behavior, including bifurcations or phase changes.
The Role of the Interpreter
: Building on the idea of context, the book might delve deeper into the role of the interpreter in understanding and explaining complex systems, discussing the importance of considering context in this role.
If you can provide more details about the book or the specific themes or questions it addresses, I'd be happy to provide more detailed analysis or explanation based on the information available up until my last training cut-off in September 2021.
1 / 1
Context Changes Everything
How Constraints Create Coherence
By Alicia Juarrero
$45.00
Paperback
eBook
296 pp., 6 x 9 in, 2 b&w illus.
Paperback
9780262545662
Published: June 20, 2023
Publisher: The MIT Press
Description
From the influential author of Dynamics in Action, how the concepts of constraints provide a way to rethink relationships, opening the way to intentional, meaningful causation.
Grounding her work in the problem of causation, Alicia Juarrero challenges previously held beliefs that only forceful impacts are causes. Constraints, she claims, bring about effects as well, and they enable the emergence of coherence. In Context Changes Everything, Juarrero shows that coherence is induced by enabling constraints, not forceful causes, and that the resulting coherence is then maintained by constitutive constraints. Constitutive constraints, in turn, become governing constraints that regulate and modulate the way coherent entities behave. Using the tools of complexity science, she offers a rigorously scientific understanding of identity, hierarchy, and top-down causation, and in so doing, presents a new way of thinking about the natural world.
Juarrero argues that personal identity, which has been thought to be conferred through internal traits (essential natures), is grounded in dynamic interdependencies that keep coherent structures whole. This challenges our ideas of identity, as well as the notion that stability means inflexible rigidity. On the contrary, stable entities are brittle and cannot persist. Complexity science, says Juarrero, can shape how we meet the world, how what emerges from our interactions finds coherence, and how humans can shape identities that are robust and resilient. This framework has significant implications for sociology, economics, political theory, business, and knowledge management, as well as psychology, religion, and theology. It points to a more expansive and synthetic philosophy about who we are and about the coherence of living and nonliving things alike.
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
Based on this description of Alicia Juarrero's book "Context Changes Everything: How Constraints Create Coherence," we can deduce the following key points that the book might discuss:
The Role of Constraints in Causation
: The author challenges the traditional notion of causation as solely based on direct, forceful impacts. Instead, she proposes that constraints (rules, regulations, limitations, etc.) also play a crucial role in bringing about effects.
Emergence and Maintenance of Coherence
: Juarrero argues that coherence, or the logical and consistent interconnection of parts in any system, is induced by enabling constraints. Furthermore, this coherence is maintained by constitutive constraints, which eventually become governing constraints that modulate the behavior of coherent entities.
Identity through Interdependencies
: The book seems to redefine personal identity not as something derived solely from internal traits, but as something grounded in dynamic interdependencies that hold
1 / 1
Continue
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
coherent structures together. This perspective may challenge traditional conceptions of identity as stable, rigid, and inflexible. Instead, Juarrero argues that truly stable entities are not rigid but rather resilient and capable of persisting through change.
The Impact of Complexity Science
: Juarrero believes that complexity science can provide a new framework for understanding the world, human interactions, and the formation of robust identities. This perspective might pave the way for more integrated and interdisciplinary ways of understanding various fields, ranging from sociology and economics to psychology and theology.
Broader Implications
: The idea of understanding identity and causation through the lens of complexity science and constraints has profound implications across various disciplines. By proposing a new way of understanding causation and coherence, Juarrero potentially introduces novel perspectives to fields such as sociology, economics, political theory, business, knowledge management, psychology, religion, and theology.
Synthetic Philosophy
: The book seems to aim for a more expansive and synthetic philosophy that can address not only our understanding of our own identities but also the coherence of both living and nonliving entities.
In summary, "Context Changes Everything" seems to focus on the idea that constraints and complexity science have a significant role in explaining causation, coherence, and identity. It attempts to provide a new framework to understand these concepts, potentially leading to novel insights across various disciplines.
1 / 1
It seems she discussed some of the same topics: Contextual Constraints and Historical Trajectory: The explanation of a phenomenon involves tracing its historical trajectory and understanding the interrelationships and dependencies formed by contextual constraints.
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
Yes, from your description and the summary of the book "Context Changes Everything", it's clear that some overarching themes and ideas appear both in the book and in your initial excerpt. These include:
Role of Contextual Constraints
: Both discussions emphasize the role of contextual constraints in shaping outcomes. In the case of the book, Juarrero discusses how enabling constraints induce coherence, while in your excerpt, the author explores how contextual interactions contribute to the system's trajectory, taking it far from equilibrium and potentially leading to bifurcations or phase changes.
Historical Trajectory and Dependencies
: Both sources emphasize the importance of understanding the historical trajectory of a system or phenomenon and the dependencies formed along that trajectory. In the book, Juarrero emphasizes the role of constraints in creating coherence, which is maintained by constitutive constraints. Similarly, in the excerpt, the author highlights the importance of retracing a phenomenon's historical trajectory to provide a genealogical or historical narrative that encapsulates its dependencies.
Identity and Transformation
: Both discussions explore the theme of identity and its transformation. In your excerpt, the author talks about genealogical narratives that can reconstruct the dramatic transformation of an individual, especially in cases like addiction. Juarrero, in her book, challenges traditional ideas of personal identity as conferred through internal traits and proposes that it is grounded in dynamic interdependencies that keep coherent structures whole.
Complexity Science
: In both the book and your excerpt, complexity science is used as a lens to understand and interpret phenomena. In your excerpt, the author discusses the unpredictability of complex systems and the role of stochastic dynamics. Juarrero's book also draws on complexity science to provide a novel understanding of identity, hierarchy, and top-down causation.
It's clear that both sources approach similar topics, albeit from potentially different angles and with different foci. They share a common emphasis on the importance of contextual constraints, historical trajectories, and the insights offered by complexity science in understanding and explaining phenomena.
1 / 1
A list of everything we have talked about so far.
1 / 1
ChatGPT
ChatGPT
Absolutely! Here's a summary of all the topics we've covered in our discussion so far:
Complex Systems and Phase Changes